Results for 'Steven Louis Reynolds'

998 found
Order:
  1.  6
    Modern science and western culture: The issue of time.Steven Louis Goldman - 1982 - History of European Ideas 3 (4):371-401.
    *This paper was presented at a conference on scientific concepts of time in humanistic and social perspectives organised by J.T. Fraser and held at the Rockefeller Study Center, Bellagio, Italy, in July 1981. I wish to thank Y. Elkana, Director of the Van Leer Jerusalem Foundation and M. Ron, Curator of the history of science collections at the Jewish National Library at the Hebrew University in Jerusalem, for making facilities available to me in researching and preparing this paper.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  9
    Science and technology in the Industrial Revolution.Steven Louis Goldman - 1991 - History of European Ideas 13 (5):653-655.
  3.  1
    Revelation and Heresy in Sociobiology: a Review Essay : Present Strains in the Relations Between Science, Technology and Society. [REVIEW]Steven Louis Goldman - 1979 - Science, Technology and Human Values 4 (2):44-51.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Justification as the appearance of knowledge.Steven L. Reynolds - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 163 (2):367-383.
    Adequate epistemic justification is best conceived as the appearance, over time, of knowledge to the subject. ‘Appearance’ is intended literally, not as a synonym for belief. It is argued through consideration of examples that this account gets the extension of ‘adequately justified belief’ at least roughly correct. A more theoretical reason is then offered to regard justification as the appearance of knowledge: If we have a knowledge norm for assertion, we do our best to comply with this norm when we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  5.  26
    Transformation and tradition in the sciences: Essays in honor of I. Bernard Cohen: ed. Everett Mendelsohn , 577 pp., £40.00, $59.50. [REVIEW]Steven Louis Goldman - 1987 - History of European Ideas 8 (1):99-100.
  6.  14
    The concept of a physical law: Norman Swarz . 220 pp., S29.95, £22.50. [REVIEW]Steven Louis Goldman - 1987 - History of European Ideas 8 (1):97-99.
  7. Proxy Functions and Inscrutability of Reference.Steven L. Reynolds - 1994 - Analysis 54 (4):228 - 235.
    Objection to Quine's argument for the inscrutability of reference. The proxy functions don't preserve the relations to experience, contrary to Quine's claims.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Effective Sceptical Hypotheses.Steven L. Reynolds - 2012 - Theoria 79 (3):262-278.
    The familiar Cartesian sceptical arguments all involve an explanation of our experiences. An account of the persuasive power of the sceptical arguments should explain why this is so. This supports a diagnosis of the error in Cartesian sceptical arguments according to which they mislead us into regarding our perceptual beliefs as if they were justified as inferences to the best explanation. I argue that they have instead a perceptual justification that does not involve inference to the best explanation and that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Jean-Paul Sartre: Key Concepts (Kindle e-book edition).Steven Churchill & Jack Reynolds (eds.) - 2013 - Durham: Routledge.
    Most readers of Sartre focus only on the works written at the peak of his influence as a public intellectual in the 1940s, notably "Being and Nothingness". "Jean-Paul Sartre: Key Concepts" aims to reassess Sartre and to introduce readers to the full breadth of his philosophy. Bringing together leading international scholars, the book examines concepts from across Sartre's career, from his initial views on the "inner life" of conscious experience, to his later conceptions of hope as the binding agent for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  14
    Jean-Paul Sartre: Key Concepts.Steven Churchill & Dr Jack Reynolds (eds.) - 2013 - Durham: Routledge.
    Most readers of Sartre focus only on the works written at the peak of his influence as a public intellectual in the 1940s, notably "Being and Nothingness". "Jean-Paul Sartre: Key Concepts" aims to reassess Sartre and to introduce readers to the full breadth of his philosophy. Bringing together leading international scholars, the book examines concepts from across Sartre's career, from his initial views on the "inner life" of conscious experience, to his later conceptions of hope as the binding agent for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  68
    Sartre's Legacy.Steven Churchill & Jack Reynolds (eds.) - 2013 - New York: Routledge.
    Examines Sartre's reception and legacy, both within France and beyond.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Testimony, knowledge, and epistemic goals.Steven L. Reynolds - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 110 (2):139 - 161.
    Various considerations are adduced toshow that we require that a testifier know hertestimony. Such a requirement apparentlyimproves testimony. It is argued that the aimof improving testimony explains why we have anduse our concept of knowledge. If we were tointroduce a term of praise for testimony, usingit at first to praise testimony that apparentlyhelped us in our practical projects, it wouldcome to be used as we now use the word``know''.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  13.  16
    Knowledge as Acceptable Testimony.Steven Reynolds - 2017 - Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
    Standard philosophical explanations of the concept of knowledge invoke a personal goal of having true beliefs, and explain the other requirements for knowledge as indicating the best way to achieve that goal. In this highly original book, Steven L. Reynolds argues instead that the concept of knowledge functions to express a naturally developing kind of social control, a complex social norm, and that the main purpose of our practice of saying and thinking that people 'know' is to improve (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  14. Fairness versus Welfare.Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell - 2002 - Law and Philosophy 23 (1):73-102.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  15. Is lookism unjust?: The ethics of aesthetics and public policy implications.Louis Tietje & Steven Cresap - 2005 - Journal of Libertarian Studies 19 (2):31-50.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  16. Fairness versus Welfare.Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (215):345-348.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  17.  86
    Knowing how to believe with justification.Steven L. Reynolds - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 64 (3):273-292.
    Non-propositional experiences can help justify beliefs, contrary to recent claims made by Donald Davidson and Laurence Bonjour. It is argued that a perceptual belief is justified if there are no undermining beliefs and it was arrived at in response to an experience through an adequate exercise of properly learned recognitional skills.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  18. Imagining oneself to be another.Steven L. Reynolds - 1989 - Noûs 23 (5):615-633.
    Imagining that I am Napoleon is not (normally) imagining an impossibility. It is (or at least may be) just adopting a first person way of imagining Napoleon. The images and bits of narrative using 'I' are intended to refer to Napoleon and his surroundings, in something like the way that a salt shaker can stand for a regiment of troops when the general says "This is the third regiment' while explaining his plans at the breakfast table.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  19.  94
    Why we should prefer knowledge.Steven L. Reynolds - 2008 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 32 (1):79-93.
    This paper discusses Plato’s question from the Meno : Why should we prefer knowledge that p over mere true belief that p? I find I just do prefer knowledge, and not for any further benefit that I am aware of in the particular case. But I should have that preference, because given our practice of approving of testimony only if uttered with knowledge, I could fail to prefer knowledge, when other things seem to me to be equal, only by having (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20. Self-recognition.Steven L. Reynolds - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (167):182-190.
    This paper attempts to give an experiential explanation of the phenomenon of immunity to error through misidentification in some of our judgments about ourselves. The main idea is that in most of these judgments we respond to the type of presentation -- e.g., proprioceptive -- and not to presented properties of the perceived object.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  65
    Making up the truth.Steven L. Reynolds - 2009 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (3):315-335.
    A recent account of the meaning of 'real' leads to a view of what anti-realism should be that resembles fictionalism, while not being committed to fictionalism as such or being subject to some of the more obvious objections to that view. This account of anti-realism explains how we might 'make up' what is true in areas such as mathematics or ethics, and yet these made-up truths are resistant to alterations, even by our collective decisions. Finally it is argued that the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. The argument from illusion.Steven L. Reynolds - 2000 - Noûs 34 (4):604-621.
    In an attempt to revive discussion of the argument from illusion this paper amends the classic version of the argument to avoid Austin's main objection. It then develops and defends a version of the intentional object reply to the argument, arguing that an "unendorsed story" account of reports of dreams and hallucinations avoids commitment to nonexistent objects.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. Variation and Selection in Psychopathology and Psychotherapy: The Example of Psychological Inflexibility.Steven C. Hayes & Jean-Louis Monestès - 2018 - In David Sloan Wilson, Steven C. Hayes & Anthony Biglan (eds.), Evolution & contextual behavioral science: an integrated framework for understanding, predicting, & influencing human behavior. Oakland, Calif.: Context Press, an imprint of New Harbinger Publications.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  29
    Knowledge acquisition and asymmetry between language comprehension and production: Dolphins and apes as general models for animals.Louis M. Herman & Steven N. Austad - 1996 - In Colin Allen & D. Jamison (eds.), Readings in Animal Cognition. MIT Press. pp. 289--306.
  25.  38
    Moral rules, the moral sentiments, and behavior: Toward a theory of an optimal moral system.Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell - manuscript
    How should moral sanctions and moral rewards - the moral sentiments involving feelings of guilt and of virtue - be employed to govern individuals' behavior if the objective is to maximize social welfare? In the model that we examine, guilt is a disincentive to act and virtue is an incentive because we assume that they are negative and positive sources of utility. We also suppose that guilt and virtue are costly to inculcate and are subject to certain constraints on their (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  56
    Reply to Ripstein: Notes on welfarist versus deontological principles.Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell - 2004 - Economics and Philosophy 20 (1):209-215.
    In Fairness versus Welfare (FVW), we advance the thesis that social policies should be assessed entirely with regard to their effects on individuals' well-being. That is, no independent weight should be accorded to notions of fairness such as corrective or retributive justice or other deontological principles. Our claim is based on the demonstration that pursuit of notions of fairness has perverse effects on welfare, on other problematic aspects of the notions, and on a reconciliation of our thesis with the evident (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Why We Should Prefer Knowledge.Steven L. Reynolds - 1981 - In Felicia Ackerman (ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 79–93.
    This chapter contains sections titled: References.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Doxastic Voluntarism and the Function of Epistemic Evaluations.Steven L. Reynolds - 2011 - Erkenntnis 75 (1):19-35.
    Control of our own beliefs is allegedly required for the truth of epistemic evaluations, such as S ought to believe that p , or S ought to suspend judgment (and so refrain from any belief) whether p . However, we cannot usually believe or refrain from believing at will. I agree with a number of recent authors in thinking that this apparent conflict is to be resolved by distinguishing reasons for believing that give evidence that p from reasons that make (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  54
    Evaluational illusions and skeptical arguments.Steven L. Reynolds - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (3):529-558.
    A traditional diagnosis of the error in the Cartesian skeptical arguments holds that they exploit our tendencies to take a representationalist view of perception. Thinking (perhaps not too clearly) that we perceive only our own sensory states, it seems to us that our perceptual beliefs about physical objects must be justified qua explanations of those sensory states. Such justification requires us to have reasons to reject rival explanations, such as the skeptical hypotheses, which we lack. However, those who adopt the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  22
    Evaluational Illusions and Skeptical Arguments.Steven L. Reynolds - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (3):529-558.
    A traditional diagnosis of the error in the Cartesian skeptical arguments holds that they exploit our tendencies to take a representationalist view of perception. Thinking (perhaps not too clearly) that we perceive only our own sensory states, it seems to us that our perceptual beliefs about physical objects must be justified qua explanations of those sensory states. Such justification requires us to have reasons to reject rival explanations, such as the skeptical hypotheses, which we lack. However, those who adopt the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  18
    Irreconcilable Foundations.Steven Cresap & Louis Tietje - 2012 - Cultura 9 (1):57-72.
    Moral educators are faced with a number of polarizing trends, both in the political divide between liberals and conservatives and in the ideological divide between moral reasoners and character educators. Recent empirical research in psychology and anthropology, as exemplified in the work of Jonathan Haidt, has indicated that both kinds of polarization may have an evolutionary foundation. Our contribution is to evaluate the philosophical implications of such findings, and to place them within the cultural history of moral education. We also (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Realism and the meaning of 'real'.Steven L. Reynolds - 2006 - Noûs 40 (3):468–494.
    A new account of the semantic function (character) of ‘real’ and ‘really’ is defended. ‘Really’ as a sentential operator typically indicates that a report of what has been represented elsewhere ends and subsequent discourse is to be taken as making claims about the world. ‘Real’ and ‘really’ as applied to nouns or predicate phrases indicate that something is not being called an F merely because it represents an F. A way of drawing the distinction between realism and anti-realism based on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33. Skeptical hypotheses and 'omniscient' interpreters.Steven L. Reynolds - 1993 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (2):184 – 195.
    An attempt to defend Davidson's omniscient interpreter argument against various attempts to show that it does not succeed in showing that most of our beliefs must be true. It doesn't argue that this is a good answer to skepticism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  48
    Music as a coevolved system for social bonding.Patrick E. Savage, Psyche Loui, Bronwyn Tarr, Adena Schachner, Luke Glowacki, Steven Mithen & W. Tecumseh Fitch - 2021 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 44:e59.
    Why do humans make music? Theories of the evolution of musicality have focused mainly on the value of music for specific adaptive contexts such as mate selection, parental care, coalition signaling, and group cohesion. Synthesizing and extending previous proposals, we argue that social bonding is an overarching function that unifies all of these theories, and that musicality enabled social bonding at larger scales than grooming and other bonding mechanisms available in ancestral primate societies. We combine cross-disciplinary evidence from archeology, anthropology, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  35.  39
    Descartes and First Person Authority.Steven L. Reynolds - 1992 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 9 (2):181-189.
    Although Descartes apparently needs first person authority for his anti-skeptical project, his scattered remarks on it appear to be inconsistent. Why did he neglect this issue? According to E M Aurley, Descartes was answering Pyrrhonian skeptics, who could not consistently challenge him on it. This paper argues instead that Descartes assumed that his first person premises were certain qua clear and distinct perceptions, leaving first person authority a side issue.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Gareth B. Matthews, Thought's Ego in Augustine and Descartes Reviewed by.Steven L. Reynolds - 1993 - Philosophy in Review 13 (5):245-247.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. The model theoretic argument, indirect realism, and the causal theory of reference objection.Steven L. Reynolds - 2003 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 84 (2):146-154.
    Abstract: Hilary Putnam has reformulated his model-theoretic argument as an argument against indirect realism in the philosophy of perception. This new argument is reviewed and defended. Putnam’s new focus on philosophical theories of perception (instead of metaphysical realism) makes better sense of his previous responses to the objection from the causal theory of reference. It is argued that the model-theoretic argument can also be construed as an argument that holders of a causal theory of reference should adopt direct realism in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  58
    The Phenomenology of Anomalous World Experience in Schizophrenia: A Qualitative Study.Elizabeth Pienkos, Steven Silverstein & Louis Sass - 2017 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 48 (2):188-213.
    This current study is a pilot project designed to clarify changes in the lived world among people with diagnoses within the schizophrenia spectrum. The Examination of Anomalous World Experience was used to interview ten participants with schizophrenia spectrum disorders and a comparison group of three participants with major depressive disorder. Interviews were analyzed using the descriptive phenomenological method. This analysis revealed two complementary forms of experience unique toszparticipants: Destabilization, the experience that reality and the intersubjective world are less comprehensible, less (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39.  25
    Book review. [REVIEW]Louis Tietje & Steven Cresap - 2006 - Journal of Value Inquiry 40 (4):505-513.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  32
    Paulo Barone, Eta della polvere: Giacometti, Heidegger, Kant, Hegel, Schopenhauer e 10 spazio estetico della caducita (Venice: Marsilio, 1999). Warren Breckman, Marx, the Young Hegelians, and the Origins of Radical Social Theory: Dethroning the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). Paul Diesing, Hegel's Dialectical Political Economy: A Contemporary Application (Boul. [REVIEW]Steven Hicks, Bernard Mabille, Alan Patten, Raymond Plant, Fabrizio Ravaglioli, Herbert Schnadelbach & Jean-Louis Vieillard-Baron - 1999 - The Owl of Minerva 31 (1).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Gareth B. Matthews, Thought's Ego in Augustine and Descartes. [REVIEW]Steven Reynolds - 1993 - Philosophy in Review 13:245-247.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  21
    Mental Reality. [REVIEW]Steven L. Reynolds - 1997 - International Studies in Philosophy 29 (4):144-145.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  7
    Toward inclusive theories of the evolution of musicality.Patrick E. Savage, Psyche Loui, Bronwyn Tarr, Adena Schachner, Luke Glowacki, Steven Mithen & W. Tecumseh Fitch - 2021 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 44:e121.
    We compare and contrast the 60 commentaries by 109 authors on the pair of target articles by Mehr et al. and ourselves. The commentators largely reject Mehr et al.'s fundamental definition of music and their attempts to refute (1) our social bonding hypothesis, (2) byproduct hypotheses, and (3) sexual selection hypotheses for the evolution of musicality. Instead, the commentators generally support our more inclusive proposal that social bonding and credible signaling mechanisms complement one another in explaining cooperation within and competition (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  21
    Memory and the brain: A retrospective.Heather Bortfeld, Steven M. Smith & Louis G. Tassinary - 2006 - Cognition and Emotion 20 (7):1027-1045.
  45.  19
    Analyses et comptes rendus.Myriam Bienenstock, Henri Dilberman, Roselyne Dégremont, Patrick Cerutti, Alain Panero, Jacqueline Carroy, Jean-Louis Vieillard-Baron, Stéphanie Roza, Stanislas Deprez, Jean-Pierre Richard, Roberto Zambiasi, Jean-Claude Dumoncel, Francesco Saverio Nisio, Vincent Blanchet, Bernard Stevens, Claudia Serban, Alexandre Declos & Michel Kail - 2022 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 147 (3):377-424.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Dialogue on Psychopathology and Behavior Change.Participants: Renée Duckworth, Steven C. Hayes, Jean-Louis Monestès & David Sloan Wilson - 2018 - In David Sloan Wilson, Steven C. Hayes & Anthony Biglan (eds.), Evolution & contextual behavioral science: an integrated framework for understanding, predicting, & influencing human behavior. Oakland, Calif.: Context Press, an imprint of New Harbinger Publications.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Louis de la Forge and the development of occasionalism: Continuous creation and the activity of the soul.Steven M. Nadler - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (2):215-231.
    Louis de La Forge and the Development of Occasionalism: Continuous Creation and the Activity of the Soul STEVEN NADLER THE DOCTRINE OF DIVINE CONSERVATION is a dangerous one. It is not theologi- cally dangerous, at least not in itself. From the thirteenth century onwards, and particularly with the Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas, the notion of the continuous divine sustenance of the world of created things was, if not univer- sally accepted, a nonetheless common feature of theological orthodoxy, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48. The Occasionalism of Louis de la Forge.Steven Nadler - 1993 - In Causation in Early Modern Philosophy. Pennsylvania State University Press. pp. 57--73.
  49.  4
    The Good Cartesian: Louis de la Forge and the Rise of a Philosophical Paradigm.Steven M. Nadler - 2024 - New York, NY: Oxford University press.
    A biographical and philosophical study of Louis de La Forge (1632-1666) and his contributions to the fortunes of Cartesianism in the seventeenth century. La Forge was instrumental in making Descartes' philosophy the dominant philosophical paradigm of the period. He contributed illustrations and a commentary to the 1664 edition of Descartes' Traité de l'homme; and then, in 1666, he published his own account of the human mind and its relation to the body on Cartesian principles, the Traité de l'esprit de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  67
    Phenomenology in France: A Philosophical and Theological Introduction.Steven DeLay - 2018 - London: Routledge.
    This book is an introduction to French phenomenology in the post 1945 period. Whilst many of phenomenology's greatest thinkers - Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre and Merleau-Ponty - wrote before this period, Steven DeLay introduces and assesses the creative and important turn phenomenology took after these figures. He presents a clear and rigorous introduction to the work of relatively unfamiliar and underexplored philosophers, including Jean-Louis Chrétien, Michel Henry, Jean-Yves Lacoste, Jean-Luc Marion and others. -/- After an introduction setting out the (...)
1 — 50 / 998